A priori

From The Logic Museum
Jump to navigationJump to search

In scholastic logic, a demonstration or proof or argument is a priori when it proceeds from cause to effect. It contrasts with a posteriori demonstration, which proceeds the other way round, from effect to presumed cause. A priori knowledge is what is derived from such demonstration or reasoning, likewise knowledge a posteriori. The distinction arises in Aristotle's Posterior Analytics 89b 21. τὸ ὅτι was translated by Boethius as quia, and τὸ διότι translated as propter quid.

In modern philosophy of science, and philosophy generally, a priori argument is typically identified as deductive, or independent of experience, a posteriori as inductive or based on empirical evidence.

Derivation

'A' in Latin is 'from', and 'priori' is the ablative of 'prior', meaning 'before'. So 'a priori' is literally reasoning from what is before to what comes after, or knowledge based on such reasoning. Similarly 'a posteriori' is reasoning from what comes after to what comes before. Scholastic writers often used the term 'propter quid' for a priori, and quia for a posteriori. In chapter 17 of Part III-II of Summa Logicae, Ockham writes


Latin English
Propter quod oportet scire quod quaedam est demonstratio cuius praemissae sunt simpliciter priores conclusione, et illa vocatur demonstratio a priori sive propter quid. On account of this we must know [scire] that one sort of demonstration whose premisses are absolutely prior to the conclusion, and [that] this is called demonstration a priori or propter quid.
Quaedam est demonstratio cuius praemissae non sunt simpliciter priores conclusione, sunt tamen notiores sic syllogizanti, per quas devenit sic syllogizans in notitiam conclusionis, et talis demonstratio vocatur demonstratio quia sive a posteriori. Another sort is demonstration whose premisses are not absolutely prior to the conclusion, and which are nevertheless better known to the syllogiser in this way, through which the syllogiser thus arrives at knowledge of the conclusion. And such demonstration is called demonstration quia or a posteriori.


The exemplar of a priori reasoning is mathematical demonstration, for example from the definition of a triangle (three straight lines enclosing a space) to one of its properties (the sum of the angles is that of a straight line). So a priori reasoning is going to be deductive. By contrast, the exemplar of a posteriori reasoning is from effect to cause. Aristotle frequently gives the example of an eclipse, where we observe the effect of the sun going into shadow, and reason that its cause is the moon going in front of it. But in that case we have no direct or immediate knowledge of the cause. All we have to go by is what we observe, the effect. Since there is no logical connection between the effect and the cause, it follows that the reasoning cannot be deductive, and may well be 'inductive'.


Links