PRINCIPLES OF LOGIC

 

 

PART I

 

THE LOGIC OF THOUGHT

 

Chapter I.

THE NATURE AND AIM OF LOGIC.

 

1. Definition of Logic

2. Divisions of Logic

3. The Place of Logic in Philosophy

4. The Scope of Logic

5. The History of Logic

§ 1.  Definition of Logic. Logic may be defined as the science which directs the operations of the mind in the attainment of truth.

What do we mean by truth? An assertion is said to be true when it corresponds to the reality of which the assertion is made. But the verbal statement is merely the outward expression of the thought within. It is our thoughts which are properly said to be true or erroneous.  For present purposes, therefore, we may define truth as the conformity of the intellect with its object. Thus if I see a white horse, and judge 'That horse is white', my judgment is said to be true, because my thought corresponds with the thing about which I am judging.

The aim of all our mental operations is to attain true judgments. If I endeavour to establish a geometrical proposition, my object is to arrive in the end at a judgment, which is in conformity with reality. Now there are certain definite ways in which, and in which alone, our thinking faculty must proceed if it is to achieve its task of faithfully representing the real order. Reflection enables us to observe the operations of the mind; and hence we are able to know and to catalogue these common types of mental action. In this way we learn the rules, which we must observe in reasoning, if we are to arrive at a true result. For, as experience shows us, it is very easy to argue in a way that will bring us, not to truth, but to error.  It was a boast of the Sophists in ancient Greece that they could make the worse appear to be the better cause. They managed this end by skilfully violating the rules which men must observe, if their conclusions are to be true.

Another definition may be given of Logic, in which the science is considered in a different aspect. Logic is the science which treats of the conceptual representation of the real order; in other words, which has for its subject-matter things as they are represented in our thought.  The difference between this definition and that which we gave in the first instance, is that this definition expresses the subject-matter of Logic, while the former expresses its aim. We shall find as we proceed that the science can scarcely be understood, unless both these aspects are kept in view.

The work of Logic therefore is not to teach us some way of discovering new facts. First Francis Bacon, later Descartes, and finally, despite his admitted genius, John Stuart Mill [N1] failed to recognise this simple fact and drove logic from the confines of its valid form into the realm of the physical sciences. The discovery of things belongs to the special sciences, each in its own sphere.  Logic's purpose, on the other hand, is to assist us in the attainment of truth, because it treats of the way in which the mind represents things, and thus shows us what are those general conditions of right thinking, which must be observed whatever subject we are considering.

Where we have a systematic body of securely established principles and of conclusions legitimately drawn from these principles, there we have a science. Thus in the science of Astronomy we start from certain general laws, and have a body of conclusions derived from these. Mere facts not brought under general laws do not constitute a science. We are rightly said to have a science of Logic, for, as we shall see, it consists of a body of principles and legitimate conclusions, such as we have described.

§ 2.  Divisions of Logic. The simplest act of the mind in which it can attain truth is the judgment -- the act by which the mind affirms or denies something about something else. That which is affirmed (or denied) of the other is called an attribute: that to which it is said to belong (or not to belong) is called a subject. Hence we may define a judgment as the act by which the mind affirms or denies an attribute of a subject.

A judgment however gives the mind a complex object: for it involves these two parts -- subject and attribute. We must therefore take account of a more elementary act of the mind than judgment, viz.: Simple Apprehension.  Simple apprehension is the act by which the mind without judging, forms a concept of something. Thus if I should conceive the notion of a triangle, without however making any judgment about it, I should be said to have formed a simple apprehension of a triangle. David Hume built much of his system on blatantly denied this fact. He insisted that immediately the mind conceived of triangle it had an image of its exact type and size, i.e. scalene or isosceles. Sadly nobody tried him with a myriagon!

However, the words true or false cannot be applied to simple apprehensions, just as we cannot say that the words in a dictionary are true or false. Following Hume, some philosophers indeed deny that the mind ever forms a simple apprehension; they hold that in every case some judgment is made.  We need not even enter into this question. We can at least analyse the judgment into simple apprehensions: for every judgment requires two concepts, one in which the mind expresses the subject, and the other in which it expresses the attribute. Thus in the example given above, I must have a concept of horse, and one of whiteness, in order to say 'The horse is white'. These are the elements which go to constitute the complex act of judgment, and they can be considered in isolation from it. Logic therefore must deal with the concept.

There is a third process of the mind, namely Reasoning or Inference. This is defined as the act, by which from two given judgments, the mind passes to a third judgment distinct from these, but implicitly contained in them.  Thus if I say

All roses wither in the autumn;

This flower is a rose;

Therefore: This flower wilt wither in the autumn;

or if I argue

Whatever displays the harmonious ordering of many parts is due to an intelligent cause;

The world displays the harmonious ordering of many parts;

Therefore : The world is due to an intelligent cause;

I am said in each case to infer the third judgment. An inference of the form which we have employed in these examples, is called a syllogism. The two judgments given are known as the premisses. The judgment derived from them is the conclusion.

It is of these three acts of the mind that Logic treats: and the science falls correspondingly into three main divisions, -- the Logic (1) of the Concept, (2) of the Judgment, (3) of Inference.

Since Logic deals with thought, it necessarily takes account to some extent of language -- the verbal expression of thought. It does so however from quite a different point of view to that of Grammar.  Grammar is concerned with words as such. It is the art by which the words employed in significant speech are combined according to the conventional rules of a language.  Hence in it each of the nine parts of speech is treated independently, and rules are given for their respective use. On the other hand, the simplest object of which Logic takes account is the Concept. In its consideration of words, therefore, it does not deal with any of those parts of speech, which taken by themselves are incapable of giving us an independent concept. It is conversant not with nine, but with two forms only of significant utterance, viz.: the Name, the verbal expression of the Concept, and the Proposition, the verbal expression of the Judgment [N2].  The proposition consists of three parts.  These are, (1) the Subject -- that of which the assertion is made: (2) the Predicate -- that which is affirmed or denied of the Subject: and (3) the Copula -- the verb is or are which connects the Subject and the Predicate. The Subject and the Predicate are called the Terms (from the Latin terminus -- a boundary) of the proposition: and the predicate is said to be predicated of the subject.

§ 3.  The Place of Logic in Philosophy.  The sciences fall into two broad divisions, viz.: the speculative and the regulative (or normative) sciences. In the speculative sciences, philosophic thought deals with those things which we find proposed to our intelligence in the universe: such sciences have no other immediate end than the contemplation of the truth. Thus we study Mathematics, not primarily with a view to commercial success, but that we may know. In the normative sciences, on the other hand, the philosopher pursues knowledge with a view to the realization of some practical end. "The object of philosophy," says St. Thomas of Aquin, "is order. This order may be such as we find already existing; but it may be such as we seek to bring into being ourselves." [N3] Thus sciences exist, which have as their object the realization of order in the acts both of our will and of our intellect. The science which deals with the due ordering of the acts of the will, is Ethics, that which deals with order in the acts of the intellect is Logic.

The question has often been raised, whether Logic is science or an art. The answer to this will depend entirely on the precise meaning which we give to the word 'art.' The medieval philosophers regarded the notion of an art as signifying a body of rules by which man directs his actions to the performance of some work [N4]. Hence they held Logic to be the art of reasoning, as well as the science of the reasoning process. Perhaps a more satisfactory terminology is that at present in vogue, according to which the term 'art,' is reserved to mean a body of precepts for the production of some external result, and hence is not applicable to the normative sciences.

Aesthetics, the science which deals with beauty and proportion in the objects of the external senses, is now reckoned with Ethics and Logic, as a normative science. By the medieval writers it was treated theoretically rather than practically, and was reckoned part of Metaphysics.

It may be well to indicate briefly the distinction between Logic and two other sciences, to which it bears some affinity.

Logic and Metaphysics. The term Metaphysics sometimes stands for philosophy in general sometimes with a more restricted meaning it stands for that part of philosophy known as Ontology. In this latter sense Metaphysics deals not with thoughts, as does Logic, but with things, not with the conceptual order but with the real order. It investigates the meaning of certain notions which all the special sciences presuppose, such as Substance, Accident, Cause, Effect, Action.  It deals with principles which the special sciences do not prove, but on which they rest, such as e.g., Every event must have a cause. Hence it is called the science of Being, since its object is not limited to some special sphere, but embraces all that is, whether material or spiritual.  Logic on the other hand deals with the conceptual order, with thoughts. Its conclusions do not relate to things, but to the way in which the mind represents things.

Logic and Psychology. The object of Psychology is the human soul and all its activities. It investigates the nature and operations of intellect, will, imagination, sense. Thus its object is far wider than that of Logic, which is concerned with the intellect alone. And even in regard to the intellect, the two sciences consider it under different aspects. Psychology considers thought merely as an act of the soul. Thus if we take a judgment, such as e.g., "The three angles of a triangle are together equal to two right angles," Psychology considers it, merely in so far as it is a form of mental activity. Logic on the other hand, examines the way in which this mental act expresses the objective truth with which it deals; and if necessary, asks whether it follows legitimately from the grounds on which it is based. Moreover, Logic, as a regulative science, seeks to prescribe rules as to how we ought to think. With this Psychology has nothing to do: it only asks, What as a matter of fact is the nature of the mind's activity?

§ 4. The Scope of Logic. Logicians are frequently divided into three classes, according as they hold that the science is concerned (1) with names only, (2) with the form of thought alone, (3) with thought as representative of reality.

(1) The first of these views - that Logic is concerned with names only - has found but few defenders. It is however taught by the French philosopher Condillac (1715 - 1780), who held that the process of reasoning consists solely in verbal transformations. The meaning of the conclusion is, he thought, ever identical with that of the original proposition.

(2) The theory that Logic deals only with the forms of thought, irrespective of their relation to reality, was taught among others by Hamilton (1788 -1856) and Mansel (1820 -1871). Both of these held that Logic is no way concerned with the truth of our thoughts, but only with their consistency.

In this sense Hamilton says: "Logic is conversant with the form of thought, to the exclusion of the matter" (Lectures. I. p. xi). By these logicians a distinction is drawn between 'formal truth,' i.e., self-consistency and 'material truth,' i.e., conformity with the object and it is said that Logic deals with formal truth alone. On this view Mill well observes: "the notion of the true and false will force its way even into Formal Logic. We may abstract from actual truth, but the validity of reasoning is always a question of conditional truth - whether one proposition must be true if the others are true, or whether one proposition can be true if others are true" (Exam. of Hamilton, p. 399).

(3) According to the third theory, Logic deals with thought as the means by which we attain truth. Mill, whom we have just quoted, may stand as a representative of this view. "Logic," he says, "is the theory of valid 'thought, not of thinking, but of correct thinking" (Exam. of Hamilton, p. 388).

To which class of logicians should Aristotle and his Scholastic followers be assigned? Many modern writers rank them in the second of these groups, and term them Formal Logicians. It will soon appear on what a misconception this opinion rests, and how completely the view taken of Logic by the Scholastics differs from that of the Formal Logicians. In their eyes, the aim of the science was most assuredly not to secure self-consistency, but theoretically to know how the mind represents its object, and practically to arrive at truth.

The terms Nominalist, Conceptualist, and Realist Logicians are now frequently employed to denote these three classes. This terminology is singularly unfortunate: for the names, Nominalist, Conceptualist and Realist, have for centuries been employed to distinguish three famous schools of philosophy, divided from each other on a question which has nothing to do with the scope of Logic. In this class we shall as far as possible avoid using the terms in their novel meaning.

§ 5. The History of Logic.  It was Aristotle (384 - 322 BC) who laid the foundations of the science by treating logical questions separately from other parts of philosophy. Six of his treatises are concerned with the subject: they cover almost the whole ground.

 

1. The Categories -- a treatise on the ten primary classes into which our concepts of things are divided.

2. De Interpretatione -- a treatise on terms and propositions.

3. Prior Analytics -- a treatise on inference.

4. Posterior Analytics -- a treatise on the logical analysis of science.

5. Topics -- a treatise on the method of reasoning to be employed in philosophical questions, when demonstrative proof is not obtainable.

6. Sophistical Refutations -- an account of fallacious reasonings.

   

This group of treatises was afterwards known as the Organon. It should, however, be noticed that they are separate works. Aristotle himself had no single word to signify the whole of Logic, and it seems doubtful whether he viewed it as a single science. The name Logic was introduced by Zeno the Stoic (about 300 BC).

The successors of Aristotle added but little of permanent value to his great achievement. Enduring importance however attaches to a small treatise by the Neo-platonist Porphyry (233 - 304 AD) entitled the Isagogé or Introduction to the Categories of Aristotle.

In a certain sense the name of Boethius (B. Severinus Boethius 470 - 525 AD) constitutes a landmark in the history of Logic: for it was through the medium of his translation of the Organon, and his commentaries on the Categories and the Isagogé, that the works of Aristotle and Porphyry were available for educational purposes in Western Europe from the sixth to the thirteenth century [N5]. Through this period some knowledge of Logic was widely possessed, as it was one of the seven liberal arts - Grammar, Dialectic i.e., Logic, Rhetoric, Geometry, Arithmetic, Astronomy, and Music - of which higher education was held to consist.

At the beginning of the thirteenth century the numerous other treatises of Aristotle, and the works of his Arabian commentators Avicenna (Ibn Sina 980 - 1037 AD) and Averroes (Ibn Roshd 1126 - 1189 AD) were translated into Latin, and gave an immense impetus to philosophic study. The mediaeval Scholastics availed themselves of these works, to build up a thoroughly systematic science of Logic.  It may perhaps be said that their main advance on Aristotle's treatment lay in the greater accuracy with which they discriminated the respective spheres of Logic and Metaphysics, and in their more precise arrangement of the various parts of Logic itself.

The 15th and 16th centuries witnessed the decadence of Scholasticism, and in 1620 an attack was made on the very foundations of the Aristotelian Logic by Francis Bacon in his Novum Organum.  Much of his criticism was unfounded, since he believed that the purpose of Logic was to provide men with a means towards making discoveries regarding the laws and phenomena of nature. Yet it was of service in calling fresh attention to the theory of Induction, a part of Logic to which too little attention had been given by the later Scholastics.

Since the time of Bacon the whole question of Induction has been very fully discussed by writers on Logic. The most eminent of these among English thinkers was John Stuart Mill (1806 - 1873), whose treatment of the subject long held rank as the classical work on Induction. Many of the points, however, raised by these writers do not strictly speaking belong to the province of Logic. For, influenced by Bacon, they have dealt not merely with Induction as a process of thought, but also with a very different subject, namely the general theory of scientific investigation.  It was indeed natural that a keen interest should be felt in this question.  The rapid growth and multiplication of the physical sciences during the last three centuries could not but lead to the codification of their rules and to reflection on their methods -- in other words to the formation of a philosophy of evidence.  Such a science was impossible in the middle ages, before the great era of physical investigation had dawned. At the present day the treatment of this subject forms a part of every work on Logic. By many writers it is termed Material or Inductive Logic, the traditional part of the science receiving by way of distinction the name of Formal or Deductive Logic.  These names are misleading. The traditional Logic was, as we have seen not purely formal. And though the treatment of Induction, properly so called by many of the medieval writers, was inadequate; yet they all regarded it as falling within their scope.  We have therefore preferred to designate the two portions of this series of lectures The Logic of Thought and Applied Logic or the Method of Science respectively.  Induction as a process of thought, finds its place in the first of these two divisions.

 

NOTE TO CHAPTER ONE

DIFFERENT VIEWS AS TO THE SCOPE OF LOGIC

The difference of opinion as to the true scope of Logic is far wider than would appear from the triple division which is usually recognized in logical text-books: and special names are now employed by logicians to indicate the point of view from which the science is treated. Moreover the threefold division is, as we have noticed, open to the further objection that it compels us to group the Scholastic logicians either with the school of Mansel or with that of Mill, though they have little enough in common with either of these. It seems, therefore, desirable to enter somewhat more into detail on the subject.  It is therefore important to give a very brief explanation of the special designations referred to, viz.: Scholastic Logic, Formal Logic, Symbolic Logic, Inductive Logic, Transcendental Logic, Logic of the Pure Idea, Modern Logic.  As far as possible we have availed ourselves of citations from authors representative of the various views, in order to make clear the meaning of their different terms.

(1) Scholastic Logic. We have explained above that the Scholastic or Traditional Logic holds the subject-matter of the science to be the conceptual representation of the real order. This may be otherwise expressed by saying that it deals with things, not as they are in themselves, but as they are in thought. Cardinal Mercier says: "There are two sciences whose object is in the highest degree abstract, and hence universal in its applicability. These are Metaphysics and Logic. The object of Metaphysics is Being considered in abstraction from all individua1 determinations and material properties, in other words the Real as such. . . . Logic also has Being for its object. "It must not however be thought that Logic and Metaphysics consider Being from the same point of view. . . . The object Metaphysics is the thing considered as a real substance endowed with real attributes. The object of Logic is likewise the thing, but considered as an object of thought endowed with attributes of the conceptual order"  (Logique 23 3d ed.)

(2) Formal Logic. The characteristic of this school is to consider the mental processes in entire abstraction from the relation which the concept bears to the real order. Logic, says Dean Mansel, "accepts as valid, all such concepts, judgments and reasonings, as do not directly or indirectly imply contradictions: pronouncing them thus far to be legitimate as thoughts, that they do not in ultimate analysis destroy themselves"  (Proleg. Logica, p. 265). Mr. Keynes abstains from deciding whether Formal Logic constitutes the whole of the science, but says in its regard: "The observance of the laws which Formal Logic investigates will not do more than secure freedom from self-contradiction and inconsistency" (Formal Logic, sect; i).

(3) Symbolic Logic is a further development of Formal Logic. It is thus defined in Baldwin's Dict. of Philosophy. "Symbolic logic is that form of logic in which the combinations and relations of terms and of propositions, are represented by symbols, in such a way that the rules of a calculus may be substituted for actively conscious reasoning. Mr. Venn, its ablest exponent in this country, claims for it the great advantages, that it "generalizes the processes of the ordinary Logic" showing them as particular cases of wider problems dealing with relation (Symbolic Logic, Introd. pp. xxi - xxiii.). Though the subject has engaged the attention of several able men, it has no claim yet to be considered a science. Almost every investigator has adopted his own system of symbolic notation. It should further be mentioned, that many thinkers believe that although it affords scope for much ingenuity, it cannot possibly contribute in any way whatever to our knowledge of the reasoning process.

(4) Inductive, Empirical, Material or Applied Logic is a science developed on the basis of the views set forth in Bacon's Novum Organum. Mill terms it "a general theory of the sufficiency of Evidence," and "a philosophy of Evidence and of the Investigation of Nature" (Exam. of Hamilton, p. 402). "Everyone", he says, "who has obtained any knowledge of the physical sciences from really scientific study, knows that the questions of evidence presented . . . are such as to tax the very highest capacities of the human intellect" (ibid.) and he severely calls to task those who hold "that the problem which Bacon set before himself, and led the way towards resolving, is an impossible one . . . that the study of Nature, the search for objective truth, does not admit of any rules." Granted that there be such a science it must belong, he urges, to Logic, "for if the consideration of it does not belong to Logic, to what science does it belong?" (ibid. p. 400). It is manifest that the science Mill here describes, differs essentially from Logic, as heretofore it had been understood. This philosophy of evidence deals, not with thought, but with things as they are in the real order; and its function is to prescribe the due methods of enquiry in each several science - not merely in the physical sciences as this passage might suggest. H. Spencer with more consistency than Mill refuses altogether the name of Logic to the traditional science of that name, and prefers to term it the Theory of Reasoning (Psychology, pt. vi., c. viii.).

(5) Transcendental Logic is the name given by Kant to the most fundamental portion of his Critical Philosophy. Kant started with the assumption that all our knowledge, whether sensitive or intellectual, is internal to the mind - that we have no immediate knowledge of the external world. He further assumed that the material of all our knowledge can be nought but successive pulses of sensation without unity of any kind. If these purely subjective feelings undergo such a transmutation within us as to present to our experience an orderly world of matter and motion, this must be in virtue of an a priori element - an internal mechanism providing certain 'forms' according to which we perceive, think and reason. In the Transcendental Aesthetic - the work in which he treats of sensible perception - he endeavours to show that space and time are the 'forms' of our sensitive faculty, while the pulses of sensation constitute its matter. In the Transcendental Logiche deals with the 'forms' of intellect (Transcendental Analytic), and of reasoning (Transcendental Dialectic). The intellectual forms will be noticed later. He gave them the name of Categories, a term employed in a very different sense by Aristotle and his followers. They are "the regular lines imposed by the intellect, on which sensations settle down with unities, orders, sequences, identities" (Wallace, Kant, p. 70). The problems raised in the Transcendental Dialectic fall outside the scope of the present work.

(6) Logic of the Pure Idea. This is the name given by Hegel to his system. It will be sufficient for us to advert in the briefest manner to this philosophy, with which we are only concerned because of its bearing on Modern Logic. Its salient feature is the identification of Logic and Metaphysics. Hegel would not admit the existence of two orders - an order of thought and an order of reality. Thought, according to him, constitutes reality. Hence the science of the real - Metaphysics, is to be found in Logic - the science of thought: "Logic in our sense coincides with Metaphysics" (Wallace, Logic of Hegel, p. 38). The Universe has its origin in the inner necessity of the categories of thought. But thought in its fullest development - the thought of the Whole or the Absolute Idea passes over into reality. Thought becomes things, and realizes itself as the universe which we know.

Hegelianism is in fact a form of Pantheism. In it things are thoughts, and these thoughts are a Divine Mind evolving itself in the process of the Universe.

(7) Modern Logic. The treatment of logical problems known by this name owes its origin to the Hegelian Philosophy. It is plain that thinkers who deny the distinction between the order of things external to us, and the order of thought within, were bound to institute a new enquiry into the nature of those mental acts, which had hitherto been regarded as representative of the real order. The principal exponents of Modern Logic in England are Mr. Bradley and Mr. Bosanquet: Their work, however, is very largely based on that of the eminent German logicians Lotze and Sigwart. According to Mr. Bosanquet the only difference between Logic and Metaphysics lies in the aspect under which they view the same subject matter. "I make no doubt," he says, "that in content Logic is one with Metaphysics, and differs if at all simply in mode of treatment - in tracing the evolution of knowledge in the light of its value and import instead of attempting to summarise its value and import apart from the details of its evolution" (Logic, I. 248). The operations of the mind - judgment and reasoning - are according to this view regarded as vital functions, by which the totality we call "the real world" is intellectually constituted. The task of Logic is to analyse the process of constitution (ibid. p3).

 

 


Footnotes

 

 [N1] Mill actually established a magnificent philosophy of evidence by perfecting Aristotle's method of inductive reasoning, which we will examine later.

[N2] Cf. Boethius, Introduct. ad Syll. Cat. (Migne P. L. vol. 64, col. y66. A), and De Syll. Cat. lib. 1. (ibid. col. 766. D). Another important difference between Logic and Grammar is to be found in the fact that Logic is concerned with but one mood -- the Indicative, Grammar with all the moods equally.

[N3] St. Thomas in Ethic. I. lect. 1. Sapientis est ordinare. . . . Ordo autem quadrupliciter ad rationem comparatur. Est enim quidam ordoquem ratio non facit sed solum considerat, sicut est ordo rerum naturalium. Alius autem est ordo quem ratio considerando facit in proprio actu, puta cum ordinat conceptus suos ad invicem et signa conceptuum quae sunt voces significativae. Tertius autem est ordo quem ratio considerando facit in operationibus voluntatis. Quartus autem est ordo quem ratio considerando facit in exterioribus rebus, quarum ipsa est causa, sicut in arca et domo.

[N4] St. Thomas in An. Post. I., lect. x. "Nihil enim aliud ars esse videtur, quam certa ordinatio rationis qua per determinata media ad debitum finem actus humani perveniunt."

[N5] Two works attributed to St. Augustine were also recognized authorities at this period. St. Augustine's interest in the science was not shared by all the fathers, we are told of St. Ambrose, that he used to exclaim "A Logica Augustini, libera me Domine".

Chapter II

 


EDWARD BUCKNER'S WEBSITE

Copyright © E.D.Buckner 2005.